When was perpetual peace written




















Kant demands, to a certain extent, the moral regeneration of man. There must be perfect honesty in international dealings, good faith in the interpretation and fulfilment of treaties and so on Art.

This is a question of self-interest as well as of ethics. On the civil and religious liberty of a state depends its commercial success. Kant saw the day coming, when industrial superiority was to be identified with political pre-eminence.

The state which does not look to the enlightenment and liberty of its subjects must fail in the race. But the advantages of a high state of civilisation are not all negative. The more highly developed the individuals who form a state, the more highly developed is its consciousness of its obligations to other nations. In the ignorance and barbarism of races lies the great obstacle to a reign of law among states.

Uncivilised states cannot be conceived as members of a federation of Europe. This is the path which reason marks out. The treatise on Perpetual Peace seems to be in this respect more practical than the Idea for a Universal History.

But it matters little which way we take it. The point of view is the same in both cases: the end remains the development of man towards good, the order of his steps in this direction is indifferent.

The history of the human race, viewed as a whole, Kant regards as the realisation of a hidden plan of nature to bring about a political constitution internally and externally perfect—the only condition under which the faculties of man can be fully developed.

Does experience support this theory? Kant thought that, to a certain degree, it did. This conviction was not, however, a fruit of his experience of citizenship in Prussia, an absolute dynastic state, a military monarchy waging perpetual dynastic wars of the kind he most hotly condemned.

This was partly because of his sympathy with republican doctrines: partly due to his love of justice and peculiar hatred of war, [58] a hatred based, no doubt, not less on principle than on a close personal experience of the wretchedness it brings with it.

Looking beyond [p. In this growing influence on the state of the mass of the people who had everything to lose in war and little to gain by victory, he saw the guarantee of a future perpetual peace.

Other forces too were at work to bring about this consummation. There was a growing consciousness that war, this costly means of settling a dispute, is not even a satisfactory method of settlement. Hazardous and destructive in its effect, it is also uncertain in its results. Victory is not always gain; it no longer signifies a land to be plundered, a people to be sold to slavery. It brings fresh responsibilities to a nation, at a time when it is not always strong enough to bear them.

But, above all, Kant saw, even at the end of the eighteenth century, the nations of Europe so closely bound together by commercial interests that a war—and especially a maritime war where the scene of conflict cannot be to the same extent localised as on land—between any two of them could not but seriously affect the prosperity of the others.

This scheme of a federation of the nations of the world, in accordance with principles which would put an end to war between them, was one whose interest for Kant seemed to increase during the last twenty years of his life. Its realisation is the realisation of the highest good—the ethical and political summum bonum , for here the aims of morals and politics coincide: only in a perfect development of his faculties in culture and in morals can man at last find true happiness. History is working towards the consummation of this end.

A moral obligation lies on man to strive to establish conditions which bring its realisation nearer. It is the duty of statesmen to form a federative union as it was formerly the duty of individuals to enter the state. It is an ideal. He states plainly that he so regards it [61] and that as such it is unattainable. But this is the essence of all ideals: they have not the less value in shaping the life and character of men and nations on that account.

They are not ends to be realised but ideas according to which we must live, regulative principles. We cannot, says Kant, shape our life better than in acting as if such ideas of reason have objective validity and there be an immortal life in which man shall live according to the laws of reason, in peace with his neighbour and in freedom from the trammels of sense.

Hence we are concerned here, not with an end, but with the means by which we might best set about attaining it, if it were attainable. This is the subject matter of the Treatise on Perpetual Peace , a less eloquent and less purely philosophical essay than that of , but throughout more systematic and practical.

We have to do, not with the favourite dream of philanthropists like St. Pierre and Rousseau, but with a statement of the conditions on the fulfilment of which the transition to a reign of peace and law depends. These means are of two kinds. In the first place, what evils must we set about removing?

What are the negative conditions? And, secondly, what are the general positive conditions which will make the realisation of this idea possible and guarantee the permanence of an international peace once attained?

These negative and positive conditions Kant calls Preliminary and Definitive Articles respectively, the whole essay being carefully thrown into the form of a treaty.

The Preliminary Articles of a treaty for perpetual peace are based on the principle that anything that hinders or threatens the peaceful co-existence of nations must be abolished.

These conditions have been classified by Kuno Fischer. Kant, he points out, [62] examines the principles of right governing the different sets of circumstances in which nations find themselves—namely, a while they are actually at war; b when the time comes to conclude a treaty of peace; c when they are living in a state of peace.

The six Preliminary Articles fall naturally into these groups. War must not be conducted in such a manner as to increase national hatred and embitter a future [p. A nation may commit this injury in two ways: 1 indirectly, by causing danger to others through the growth of its standing army Art.

The National Debt Art. But, besides, we have the danger of actual attack. There is no right of intervention between nations. For a similar reason, armed troops cannot be hired and sold as things. These then are the negative conditions of peace. The right to free means of international communication has in the last hundred years become a commonplace of law. And the change has been brought about, as Kant anticipated, not through an abstract respect for the idea of right, but through the pressure of purely commercial interests.

What Kant understands by this term is that, in the state, law should rule above force and that its [p. A constitutional monarchy like that of Prussia in the time of Frederick the Great, who regarded himself as the first servant of the state and ruled with the wisdom and forethought which the nation would have had the right to demand from such an one—such a monarchy is not in contradiction to the idea of a true republic.

That the state should have a constitution in accordance with the principles of right is the essential point. Otherwise we have despotism. Hence, while Kant admitted absolutism under certain conditions, he rejected democracy where, in his opinion, the mass of the people was despot.

An internal constitution, firmly established on the principles of right, would not only serve to kill the seeds of national hatred and diminish the likelihood of foreign war.

It would do more: it would destroy sources of revolution and discontent within the state. Kant, like many writers on this subject, does not directly allude to civil war [73] and [p. Actually to achieve this would be impossible: it is beyond the power of either arbitration or disarmament. But in a representative government and the liberty of a people lie the greatest safeguards against internal discontent.

Civil peace and international peace must to a certain extent go hand in hand. We come now to the central idea of the treatise: c the law of nations must be based upon a federation of free states. The problem here is not out of many nations to make one. This would be perhaps the surest way to attain peace, but it is scarcely practicable, and, in certain forms, it is undesirable.

Kant is inclined to approve of the separation of nations by language and religion, by historical and social tradition and physical boundaries: nature seems to condemn the idea of a universal monarchy.

This scheme of a perpetual peace had not escaped ridicule in the eighteenth century: the name of [p. The facts of history, even more conclusively than the voices of philosophers, soldiers and princes, show how great has been the progress of this idea in recent years. But it has not gained its present hold upon the popular mind without great and lasting opposition.

Indeed we have here what must still be regarded as a controversial question. There have been, and are still, men who regard perpetual peace as a state of things as undesirable as it is unattainable. For such persons, war is a necessity of our civilisation: it is impossible that it should ever cease to exist.

All that we can do, and there is no harm, nor any contradiction in the attempt, is to make wars shorter, fewer and more humane: the whole question, beyond this, is without practical significance. Others, on the other hand,—and these perhaps more thoughtful—regard war as hostile to culture, an evil of the worst kind, although a necessary evil. In peace, for them, lies the true ideal of humanity, although in any perfect form this cannot be realised in the near future.

The welfare of a state, he held, is its own highest law; and he refused to admit that this welfare was to be sought in an international peace. Hegel lived in an age when all power and order seemed to lie with the sword. Something of the charm of Napoleonism seems to hang over him. He does not go the length of writers like Joseph de Maistre, who see in war the finger of God or an arrangement for the survival of the fittest—a theory, as far as regards individuals, quite in contradiction with the real facts, which show that it is precisely the physically unfit whom war, as a method of extermination, cannot reach.

But, like Schiller and Moltke, Hegel sees in war an educative instrument, developing virtues in a nation which could not be fully developed otherwise, much as pain and suffering bring patience and resignation and other such qualities into play in the individual , and drawing the nation together, making each citizen conscious of his citizenship, as no other influence can. War, he holds, leaves a nation always stronger than it was before; it buries causes of inner dissension, and consolidates the [p.

With this last statement most people will be inclined to agree. Money is a great deal: it is a necessity; but what we call national back-bone and character is more. So far we are with Hegel. But he goes further. In peace, says he, mankind would grow effeminate and degenerate in luxury. This opinion was expressed in forcible language in his own time by Schiller, [78] and in more [p.

During war are developed the noblest virtues which belong to man—courage and self-denial, fidelity to duty and the spirit of self-sacrifice: the soldier is called upon to risk his life. Without war the world would sink in materialism.

War, if too quickly over, could not have the great moral influence which has been attributed to it. The explanation may be that it is not all that it naturally appears to a great and successful general. Hegel, Moltke, Trendelenburg, Treitschke [82] and the others—not Schiller [83] who was able to sing the blessings of peace as eloquently as of war—were apt to forget that war is as efficient a school for forming vices as virtues; and that, moreover, those virtues which military life is said to cultivate—courage, self-sacrifice and the rest—can be at least as perfectly developed in other trials.

There are in human life dangers every day bravely met and overcome which are not less terrible than those which face the soldier, in whom patriotism may be less a sentiment than a duty, and whose cowardice must be dearly paid. The Peace Societies of our century, untiring supporters of a point of view diametrically opposite [p. The years of peace which followed the downfall of Napoleon had brought immense increase in material wealth to countries like France and Britain.

Something of the glamour had fallen away from the sword of the great Emperor. The illusive excitement of a desire for conquest had died: the glory of war had faded with it, but the burden still remained: its cost was still there, something to be calmly reckoned up and not soon to be forgotten. Europe was seen to be actually moving towards ruin.

New conditions had altered it in other directions. The romance and picturesqueness with which it was invested in the days of hand-to-hand combat was gone. But, above all, war was now waged for questions fewer and more important than in the time of Kant.

Our modern national wars exact a sacrifice, necessarily much more heavy, much more reluctantly made than those of the past which were fought with mercenary troops.

Such wars have not only greater dignity: they are more earnest, and their issue, as in a sense the issue of conflict between higher and lower types of civilisation, is speedier and more decisive. The strides made in recent years by commerce and the growing power of the people in every state have had much of the influence which he foretold.

There is a greater reluctance to wage [p. War has now become popular for the first time. It is in the contemplation of facts and conflicting tendencies like these that Peace Societies [86] have been formed. The peace party is, we may say, an eclectic body: it embraces many different sections of political opinion. There are those who hold, for instance, that peace is to be established on a basis of communism of property.

There are others who insist on the establishment throughout Europe of a republican form of government, or again, on a [p. But these are not the fundamental general principles of peace workers. The members of this party agree in rejecting the principle of intervention, in demanding a complete or partial disarmament of the nations of Europe, and in requiring that all disputes between nations—and they admit the prospects of dispute—should be settled by means of arbitration.

In how far are these principles useful or practicable? There is a strong feeling in favour of arbitration on the part of all classes of society. It is cheaper under all circumstances than war. It is a judgment at once more certain and more complete, excluding as far as possible the element of chance, leaving irritation perhaps behind it, but none of the lasting bitterness which is the legacy of every war.

Arbitration has an important place in all peace projects except that of Kant, whose federal union would naturally fulfil the function of a tribunal of arbitration. Pierre, Jeremy Bentham, [87] [p.

A number of cases have already been decided by this means. But let us examine the questions which have been at issue. Of a hundred and thirty matters of dispute settled by arbitration since cf. International Tribunals , published by the Peace Society, it will be seen that all, with the exception of one or two trifling cases of doubt as to the succession to certain titles or principalities, can be classified roughly under two heads—disputes as to the determination of boundaries or the possession of certain territory, and questions of claims for compensation and indemnities due either to individuals or states, arising from the seizure of fleets or merchant vessels, the insult or injury to private persons and so on—briefly, questions of money or of territory.

That they should have been settled in this way, however, shows a great advance. Smaller causes than these have made some of the bloodiest wars in history.

That arbitration should have been the means of preventing even one war which would otherwise have been waged is a strong reason why we should fully examine its claims. Arbitration is a method admirably adapted to certain cases: to those we have named, where it has been successfully applied, to the interpretation of contracts, to offences against the Law of Nations—some writers say to trivial questions of honour—in all cases where the use of armed force would be impossible, as, for instance, in any quarrel in which neutralised countries [91] like Belgium or Luxembourg should take a principal part, or in a difference between two nations, such as to take an extreme case the United States and Switzerland, [p.

These cases, which we cannot too carefully examine, show that what is here essential is that it should be possible to formulate a juridical statement of the conflicting claims. In Germany the Bundestag had only power to decide questions of law. Other disputes were left to be fought out. Questions on which the existence and vital honour of a state depend—any question which nearly concerns the disputants—cannot be reduced to any cut and dry legal formula of right and wrong.

We may pass over the consideration that in some cases as in the Franco-Prussian War the delay caused by seeking mediation of any kind would deprive a nation of the advantage its state of military preparation deserved. And we may neglect the problem of finding an impartial judge on some questions of dispute, although its solution might be a matter of extreme difficulty, so closely are the interests of modern nations bound up in one another.

How could the Eastern Question, for example, be settled by arbitration? It is impossible that such a means should be sufficient for every case. Arbitration in other words may prevent war, but can never be a substitute for war.

We cannot wonder that this is so. So numerous and conflicting are the interests of states, so various are the grades of civilisation to which they have attained and the directions [p. This is above all true where the self-preservation [92] or independence of a people are concerned.

But, indeed, looking away from questions so vital and on which there can be little difference of opinion, we are apt to forget, when we allow ourselves to talk extravagantly of the future of arbitration, that every nation thinks, or at least pretends to think, that it is in the right in every dispute in which it appears cf.

Kant: Perpetual Peace , p. We talk glibly of the right and wrong of this question or of that, of the justice of this war, the iniquity of that. But what do these terms really mean? Do we know, in spite of the labour which has been spent on this question by the older publicists, which are the causes that justify a war?

Is it not true that the same war might be just in one set of circumstances and unjust in another? Practically all writers on this subject, exclusive of those who apply the biblical doctrine of non-resistance, agree in admitting that a nation is justified in defending its own existence or independence, that this is even a moral duty as it is a fundamental right of a state.

Many, especially the older writers, make the confident assertion that all wars of defence are just. But will this serve as a standard? Gibbon tells us somewhere, that Livy asserts that the Romans conquered the world in self-defence. The distinction between wars of aggression and defence is one very difficult to draw.

The cause of a nation which waits to be actually attacked is often lost: the critical moment in its defence may be past. But, indeed, we cannot judge these questions abstractly. Where a war is necessary, it matters very little whether it is just or not. Only the judgment of history can finally decide; and generally it seems at the time that both parties have something of right on their side, something perhaps too of wrong.

A consideration of difficulties like these brings us to a realisation of the fact that the chances are small that a nation, in the heat of a dispute, will admit the likelihood of its being in the wrong. To refuse to admit this is generally tantamount to a refusal to submit the difficulty to arbitration.

And neither international law, nor the moral force of public opinion can induce a state to act contrary to what it believes to be its own interest.

Moreover, as international law now stands, it is not a duty to have recourse to arbitration. This was made quite clear in the proceedings of the Peace Conference at the Hague in In this respect things have not advanced beyond the position of the Paris Congress of But the work of the peace party regarding the [p.

The popular feeling which they have been partly the means of stimulating has no doubt done something to influence the action of statesmen towards extreme caution in the treatment of questions likely to arouse national passions and prejudices. Arbitration has undoubtedly made headway in recent years. Britain and America, the two nations whose names naturally suggest themselves to us as future centres of federative union, both countries whose industrial interests are numerous and complicated, have most readily, as they have most frequently, settled disputes in this practical manner.

It has shown itself to be a policy as economical as it is business-like. Its value, in its proper place, cannot be overrated by any Peace Congress or by any peace pamphlet; but we have endeavoured to make it clear that this sphere is but a limited one.

But, even if this were not so and arbitration were the natural sequence of every dispute, no coercive force exists to enforce the decree of the court. The moral restraint of public opinion is here a poor substitute. Treaties, it is often said, are in the same position; but treaties have been broken, and will no doubt be broken again.

We [p. Federal troops are necessary to carry out the decrees of a tribunal of arbitration, if that court is not to run a risk of being held feeble and ineffectual. Except on some such basis, arbitration, as a substitute for war, stands on but a weak footing. The efforts of the Peace Society are directed with even less hope of complete success against another evil of our time, the crushing burden of modern armaments. We have peace at this moment, but at a daily increasing cost.

The Peace Society is rightly concerned in pressing this point. It is not enough to keep off actual war: there is a limit to the price we can afford to pay even for peace.

Vattel relates that in early times a treaty of peace generally stipulated that both parties should afterwards disarm. And there is no doubt that Kant was right in regarding standing armies as a danger to peace, not only as openly expressing the rivalry and distrust between nation and nation which Hobbes regards as the basis of international relations, but also as putting a power into the hand of a nation which it may some day have the temptation to abuse.

A war-loving, overbearing spirit in a people thrives none the worse for a consciousness that its army or navy can hold its own with any other in Europe. Were it not the case that the essence of armed peace is that a high state of efficiency should be [p.

No doubt it is due to this fact that France has kept quietly to her side of the Rhine during the last thirty years. The annexation of Alsace-Lorraine was an immediate stimulus to the increase of armaments; but otherwise, just because of this greater efficiency and the slightly stronger military position of Germany, it has been an influence on the side of peace.

We are compelled to consider carefully how a process of simultaneous disarmament can actually be carried out, and what results might be anticipated from this step, with a view not only to the present but the future. Can this be done in accordance with the principles of justice? Organisations like a great navy or a highly disciplined army have been built up, in the course of centuries, at great cost and at much sacrifice to the nation.

They are the fruit of years of wise government and a high record of national industry. Are such visible tokens of the culture and character and worth of a people to be swept away and Britain, France, Germany, Italy, Spain, Turkey to stand on the same level? And, even if no such ethical considerations should arise, on what method are [p.

The standard as well as the nature of armament depends in every state on its geographical conditions and its historical position. An ocean-bound empire like Britain is comparatively immune from the danger of invasion: her army can be safely despatched to the colonies, her fleet protects her at home, her position is one of natural defence. But Germany and Austria find themselves in exactly opposite circumstances, with the hard necessity imposed upon them of guarding their frontiers on every side.

The safety of a nation like Germany is in the hands of its army: its military strength lies in an almost perfect mastery of the science of attack. The Peace Society has hitherto made no attempt to face the difficulties inseparable from any attempt to apply a uniform method of treatment to peculiarities and conditions so conflicting and various as these.

Those who have been more conscientious have not been very successful in solving them. No careful thinker would suggest, in the face of dangers threatening from the [p. The simplest of many suggestions made—but this on the basis of universal conscription—seems to be that the number of years or months of compulsory military service should be reduced to some fixed period. But this does not touch the difficulty of colonial empires [98] like Britain which might to a certain extent disarm, like their neighbours, in Europe, but would be compelled to keep an army for the defence of their colonies elsewhere.

It is, in the meantime, inevitable that Europe should keep up a high standard of armament—this is, and even if we had European federation, would remain an absolute necessity as a protection against the yellow races, and in Europe itself there are at present elements hostile to the cause of peace.

Alsace-Lorraine, Polish Prussia, Russian Poland and Finland are still, to a considerable degree, sources of discontent and dissatisfaction. But in Russia itself lies the great obstacle to a future European peace or European federation: we can scarcely picture Russia as a reliable member of such a union. That Russia should disarm is scarcely [p. But that Europe should disarm, before Russia has attained a higher civilisation, a consciousness of its great future as a north-eastern, inter-oceanic empire, and a government more favourable to the diffusion of liberty, is still less practicable.

It is not impossible that, in the course of time, this problem may be solved and that the contribution to the federal troops of a European union may be regulated upon some equitable basis the form of which we cannot now well prophesy. European federation would likewise meet all difficulties where a risk might be likely to occur of one nation intervening to protect another.

As we have said above, p. Actually a state which is actuated by less selfish impulses is apt to lose considerably more than it [p. It is not impossible that the Powers may have yet to intervene to protect Turkey against Russia.

Such a step might well be dictated purely by a proper care for the security of Europe; but wars of this kind seem not likely to play an important part in the near future. We have said that the causes of difference which may be expected to disturb the peace of Europe are now fewer.

A modern sovereign no longer spends his leisure time in the excitement of slaying or seeing slain. He could not, if he would. His honour and his vanity are protected by other means: they play no longer an important part in the affairs of nations. The causes of war can no more be either trifling or personal. Some crises there are, which are ever likely to be fatal to peace. There present themselves, in the lives of nations, ideal ends for which everything must be sacrificed: there are rights which must at all cost be defended.

The question of civil war we may neglect: liberty and wise government are the only medicine for social discontent, and much may be hoped from that in the future. But now, looking beyond the state to the great family of civilised nations, we may say that the one certain cause of war between them or of rebellion within a future federated union will be a [p. Other causes of quarrel offer a more hopeful prospect.

Some questions have been seen to be specially fitted for the legal procedure of a tribunal of arbitration, others to be such as a federal court would quickly settle. The preservation of the balance of power which Frederick the Great regarded as the talisman of peace in Europe—a judgment surely not borne out by experience—is happily one of the causes of war which are of the past.

Wars of colonisation, such as would be an attempt on the part of Russia to conquer India, seem scarcely likely to recur except between higher and lower races. The cost is now-a-days too great. Political wars, wars for national union and unity, of which there were so many during the past century, seem at present not to be near at hand; and the integration of European nations—what may be called the great mission of war—is, for the moment, practically complete; for it is highly improbable that either Alsace-Lorraine or Poland—still less Finland—will be the cause of a war of this kind.

Our hope lies in a federated Europe. Its troops would serve to preserve law and order in the country from which they were drawn and to protect its colonies abroad; but their higher function would [p. We have carefully considered what has been attempted by peace workers, and we have now to take note that all the results of the last fifty years are not to be attributed to their conscientious but often ill-directed labour.

The diminution of the causes of war is to be traced less to the efforts of the Peace Society, except indirectly, in so far as they have influenced the minds of the masses than to the increasing power of the people themselves.

The various classes of society are opposed to violent methods of settlement, not in the main from a conviction as to the wrongfulness of war or from any fanatical enthusiasm for a brotherhood of nations, but from self-interest.

War is death to the industrial interests of a nation. It is vain to talk, in the language of past centuries, of trade between civilised countries being advanced and markets opened up or enlarged by this means. It is self-interest, the prosperity of the country—patriotism, if you will—that seems better than war.

Federation and federation alone can help out the programme of the Peace Society. It cannot be pretended that it will do everything. To state the worst at once, it will not prevent war. Even the federations of the states of Germany and America, bound together by ties of blood and language and, in the latter case, of sentiment, were not strong enough within to keep out dissension and disunion.

Why did Prussian and Hanoverian fight side by side in , though they had fought [p. Ritchie, op. Wars between different grades of civilisation are bound to exist as long as civilisation itself exists. The history of culture and of progress has been more or less a history of war.

A calm acceptance of this position may mean to certain short-sighted, enthusiastic theorists an impossible sacrifice of the ideal; but, the sacrifice once made, we stand on a better footing with regard to at least one class of arguments against a federation of the world.

Such a union will lead, it is said, to an equality in culture, a sameness of interests fatal to progress; all struggle and conflict will be cast out of the state itself; national characteristics and individuality will be obliterated; the lamb and the wolf will lie down together: stagnation will result, intellectual progress will be at an end, politics will be no more, history will stand still. This is a sweeping assertion, an alarming prophecy.

But a little thought will assure us that there is small cause for apprehension. There can be no such standstill, no millennium in human affairs. See nevertheless the First Supplement where Kant contends that nature has a hand in securing peace. See also Derrida [ 20 : ] where he notes that peace is not to be understood as a utopian concept projected into infinity.

Saner [ 70 : 50] points out that Kant is here expressing a judgment on the whole of human history, which thus far has indeed been one of either war or armistice, thus a history without peace in the strict sense.

For Levinas, ethics as first philosophy begins with the encounter of the face of the other, which places an unconditional demand on me and which he also refers to as hospitality. As Derrida [ 12 : 82] points out, peace beyond the political is to be understood as neither simply political in the traditional sense nor as simply apolitical.

Derrida [ 12 : 68] nonetheless remains ambivalent about this. As Derrida points out here, war for Levinas is always against a face, but such war would nonetheless retain a trace of the pacific welcoming of a face. XVIII, 1], distinguishes between these drives. See Derrida and Stiegler [ 25 : 81] on the relation between negotiation and invention. See similarly Shryock [ 73 : ]. See Sect. See also Rimoux [ 69 : —] for whom it is rather a question of respecting the sovereignty of states.

Perpetual peace can be achieved only through voluntary actions. There are of course internal differences between these readings, and the analysis undertaken here is not exhaustive. Brandt [ 4 : —], Gerhardt [ 35 : 94, ], Huggler [ 44 : —], Koller [ 58 : —], and Scheid [ 71 : ].

Krause [ 59 : 16] e. After the revolution a federation between republican states became a real possibility coupled with a right to hospitality. See Lutz-Bachmann [ 64 : 73], Hackel [ 39 : 76—82]. Kleingeld [ 53 ; 54 : 44, 58], Habermas [ 38 : ], Rimoux [ 69 : —], Geismann [ 32 ; 33 ].

See Rimoux [ 69 : ], and Geismann [ 32 ]. See also Derrida [ 22 : —], noting the equation of majesty and sovereignty. See Derrida [ 18 : 81], Kant [ 47 : ]. See Rimoux [ 69 : 94—95], Ebert [ 30 : —], Scheid [ 71 : ].

See De Ville [ 27 : 13—37]. See Derrida [ 9 : ; 18 : 86; 21 : 86]. Habermas [ 36 ], Douzinas [ 28 ]. See also Derrida [ 16 : ] on Einstein. Hoffe [ 42 : —; 43 : —, —]. For such a Gastrech t to be established, a generous treaty to become a temporary member of the household Hausgenossen would according to Kant be required. The surface of the earth is thus to be distinguished from what is constructed on it e.

See also Ossipow [ 66 ]. See also Derrida [ 21 : 85—86]. Levinas [ 63 : 98] similarly speaks of a messianic order where a people accepts foreigners who come to settle among them. See further Sect. Derrida fully recognises the need for certain limitations; see e.

Derrida [ 12 : 89—90]. In its legal form, hospitality is also necessarily conditional. Derrida is again not being critical of Kant in pointing to these. See Kant [ 47 : ]. This issue will be explored in more detail elsewhere. See Schmitt [ 72 : 54—55], Derrida [ 22 : 71—74]. Bischof, Sacha. Fribourg: Academic. Google Scholar. Bohman James and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann. James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann, 1— Borradori, Giovanna.

Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Brandt, Reinhard. In Immanuel Kant: Zum ewigen Frieden , ed. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Brown, Garrett W. European Journal of Political Philosophy 9 3 : — Caputo, John D.

New York: Fordham University Press. Derrida, Jacques. Alan Bass. Aporias, trans. Thomas Dutoit. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Derrida, Jacques Politics of Friendship , trans. Accessed 7 November Adieu: To Emmanuel Levinas , trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas. On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. London: Routledge. Acts of Religion. New York: Routledge. Without Alibi , trans. Paper Machine , trans. Rogues: Two Essays on Reason , trans. Thomas Dutoit and Outi Pasanen.

In The Derrida - Habermas Reader , ed. Lasse Thomassen, — Chicago: University of Chicago Press. The Gift of Death 2nd ed. David Wills. I, trans. Geoffrey Bennington. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press. II, trans. Derrida, Jacques and Anne Dufourmantelle. Of Hospitality , trans. Derrida, Jacques and Bernard Stiegler.

Echographies of Television , trans. Jennifer Bajorek. Editors: Deen K. Contents Search. Perpetual Peace: Kant. Authors Authors and affiliations Don E. How to cite. This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

Reiss H, trans: Nisbet HB. Kant I Perpetual peace and other essays trans: Humphrey T. Kant I Metaphysical elements of justice, 2nd edn.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000